Tuesday, August 26, 2025

Habermas now says that he never made a head count and never defined "vast majority"

Just a few days ago, a correspondent brought something very surprising to my attention: In a livestream which aired about 10 months ago, Dr. Gary Habermas stated that he never gave a numerical meaning to his frequent phrase "vast majority of scholars" when referring to his minimal facts and that he never did a head count for the percentage of scholars who affirm the minimal facts. The only head count that he ever did, he said, was on how many scholars affirm the empty tomb, which he does not consider a minimal fact. Watch starting here and here.

The combination of these statements makes little sense, since Habermas has always said that the reason he doesn't consider the empty tomb to be a minimal fact is that it doesn't quite meet the very high level of scholarly acceptance required for the minimal facts. This reason for not calling the empty tomb a minimal fact entails that he has in mind a higher minimal degree of acceptance that has to be met in order for something to be called a minimal fact. So his reasoning about the empty tomb is incompatible with his having (as he says in the livestream) no minimum scholarly consensus requirement in mind for calling something a minimal fact. In his recent book, a book that came out in the same year that he gave this livestream with Licona, Habermas says,

[L]ess stringency is sometimes what has separated the two lists, especially in being less severe in achieving such high percentages of scholarly agreement than the near-unanimous requirements for the events in the shorter list. Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 93). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.

He says something almost verbatim the same on pp. 22-23 in 2012, here.

Moreover, how could he know that the things he does consider minimal facts are affirmed by the "vast majority" of scholars but that the empty tomb doesn't meet that higher "vast" requirement if he didn't do at least some kind of head count on both? Since he has repeatedly said, and apparently acknowledges in the livestream that he has said, that the empty tomb is affirmed by 75% to 80% of scholars, a mere guesstimate or gestalt impression wouldn't distinguish this from something still higher, required for minimal fact status. (For this percent on the empty tomb, see p. 462, Kindle location 12907, of his recent volume 1 on the resurrection. See also Dr. Licona's reference to Habermas's estimates on the empty tomb in his 2010 book on the resurrection on p. 461, footnote 606.) If you were to pour out hundreds of marbles on a table and got the mere impression that a very high majority of them were white, this broad impression wouldn't give you the information to say confidently whether 80% as opposed to 90% of them were white.

To his credit, Dr. Licona pressed Dr. Habermas in the livestream, saying that they did give percentages in their jointly written book on the resurrection. Dr. Habermas dismissed this, saying laughingly that he thinks Licona wrote those parts! This is quite unfair to Dr. Licona. Regular readers will know that I have many, many disagreements and problems with Dr. Licona and his work, but in the case of their co-written resurrection book, it is certainly not true that Licona was the one asserting that virtually all scholars hold some position while Habermas was relying on Licona. If anything, it is Habermas whose unpublished, extensive scholarly survey is treated as the basis for claims about scholarly consensus in that book. See p. 74 of The Case for the Resurrection of Jesus.

That Habermas has indeed claimed a specific minimum cutoff of 90% required for a minimal fact is indubitable, making his current disclaimer not only obviously false but also truly strange. In fact (as my correspondent also pointed out to me) he makes such a claim right in his 2024 book, which was released in January of the same year in which the livestream occurred. Here is that quotation:

An oft-asked question relates to my repeated references that the “vast majority” of scholars or “virtually all” of these experts agree with this or that conclusion. Can these phrases be identified in more precise terms? In some contexts, I have already been more specific. At least when referencing the shorter list of minimal historical facts, I most frequently think in terms of a 90-something percentile head count. Of course, this only applies to those scholars who publish their views and accept the historical fact or a close approximation of it. Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 94). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.
Habermas also uses the same phrase, "ninety-something percent," on p. 17 of this article from 2012. At one point in the livestream (here), Habermas faults philosopher Bob Stewart for having said that Habermas claims that his minimum for a minimal fact is 90 percent scholarly acceptance: "Bob's a great friend, but he thought I said 90. I've not said anything in print. People might get that idea but..." Yet a fairly simple search even of his recent work shows that he has indeed said this in print.
In his 2024 book he also repeatedly refers to counting scholars or tallying scholars in his research, as in the above reference to a "head count" and also here:
These very critical emphases should be kept in mind amid complaints that will no doubt arise from those who object to more conservative voices also being included in the counts. Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 130). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.
It is no fault of scholarship if, even after counting many of their major writings in the tallies, the research still did not favor either the mythicists or their theories! Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 130). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.
He also describes his work as charting and cataloguing scholars and their positions:
As just mentioned, if anything, one potential fault in the opposite direction included the cataloging of many of the most radical positions in the survey here. This was the only classification of sources where many of the authors rarely had the specialized scholarly credentials or relevant peer-reviewed publications to be counted in the first place. Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 100). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.
In the beginning, the study began with classifying the major publications on each of the relevant resurrection topics. This included cataloging the majority of these publications and charting the representative authors, topics, positions taken, and so on, concentrating on both well-known as well as obscure scholars alike across the entire spectrum of skeptical to liberal to moderate to conservative assessments. Habermas, Gary R. On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 99). B&H Publishing Group. Kindle Edition.
In very similar words in 2012, Habermas explicitly relates his cataloguing work to a question--whether or not his 90-something percent claim is based merely on a guess. This means that he appears to be denying that in his own case the claim is based merely on a guess or gestalt estimate:
But are figures like these based on something between a rough guess and an estimate? Academics quite often report things such as “most scholars hold that” or “the majority view here is that.” Although similar phrases are found frequently in the literature, we may wonder how the knowledge of such conclusions were, or even could be, established....To answer this question in my case, what began as a rather modest attempt to update my resurrection bibliography grew by large increments until it developed into a full-blown attempt to catalog an overview of recent scholarship. The study dominated five straight years of my research time, as well as long intermittent stretches after that. "The Minimal Facts Approach to the Resurrection of Jesus," pp. 17-18 (emphasis added)
So it is undeniable that Habermas has defined "vast majority" as 90-something percent and has strongly implied, even using words like "counts," "head count" and "tally," that he is basing this claim on his own careful cataloguing studies, not on a mere impression. He even makes such statements in his very recent publication.

One hardly knows what to make of Habermas's very emphatic and unequivocal statements in the livestream that he never made any such claims about either a percentage or a count. Some have even suggested to me that he was somehow confused. What if that is true? This would be a major, major confusion. It's hard to think of any ordinary degree of confusion, compatible with still having the mental acuity to be an active scholar still giving public interviews and lectures, that would account for this blatant contradiction between his verbal statements and his own recently published work. Something very unfortunate is going on here, one way or another.

I've already addressed the suggestion that Habermas's disavowal doesn't represent a big change in his position, since one could make a reasonable guess based on a mere gestalt impression. But he has definitely claimed the contrary; his emphasis on his care concerning the empty tomb (not counting it as a minimal fact) only stresses all the more that he has claimed something better than a vague guess concerning the percentage of scholars affirming the minimal facts.

Habermas makes another statement in the livestream meant to excuse his position (in the livestream) that he never defined minimal fact in terms of a percentage of scholars who affirm the fact. He says that if he had chosen 85% for a minimum percentage (and presumably had given references and listed scholars, so that such claims could be checked), then perhaps someone would go and find three scholars in the list and somehow refute the claim for those three (because his interpretation was wrong? because the scholars changed their minds? Habermas doesn't specify) and then say that now it's only 84%. But this is a terrible reason for not specifying what percentage one has in mind, when the agreement of "virtually all" scholars is explicitly a criterion for the use of a proposition in one's argument. What this amounts to is saying that one doesn't want to give any specific meaning to a phrase like "vast majority" or "virtually all," while still availing oneself of the rhetorical force of such phrases, lest one's claims be refuted. Making one's claims rhetorically exciting but unfalsifiable is not supposed to be a goal of scholarship!

Second, if one wants to build legitimate fuzzy edges into one's claim so that it is still falsifiable but is not poised on a knife edge, all one has to do is to pick a lower bound that is lower than one thinks the evidence actually bears. So, for example, if Habermas thought that at least 90% of scholars in his survey do affirm some minimal fact, but he thought it would be legitimate to include a fact as a "minimal fact" even if some lower percentage affirm the proposition, then all he would have to do is to pick a lower number as the lower bound. E.g. At least 85%. When choosing a lower bound, it's easy to allow a margin of error. In fact, though he doesn't recognize this in the livestream, this was presumably why he said "90-something percentile" rather than, say, 95%. If he really believed that almost every single scholar affirms some fact, close to (say) 99%, then saying "90-something percent" tells the reader what sort of standard for scholarly consensus he is using, even if he thinks the propositions in question exceed that criterion of consensus by a margin. Of course no one is going to have any grounds to criticize him merely because agreement turns out to be even greater than a lower bound he gives.

It almost seems like at this point we're going to have to distinguish "published Habermas" from "livestream Habermas" when we attribute something to him, abandoning the assumption that statements from these two sources are consistent.
Now, given all the other problems with the MFA, this is from my perspective icing on the cake (or another straw on the camel's back, or whatever metaphor you want to use). Even if Dr. Habermas had been consistent in the livestream with his own published work, claiming to have done at least a pretty good head count and claiming, as he has before, that his minimal facts are affirmed by 90-something percent of all scholars across the ideological spectrum, these other problems would remain. These would include his own major, published errors in interpreting the scholars he claims to summarize. See here, here, and the top six videos in the playlist here. Suppose that at some later point in time a document is published under Dr. Habermas's name, purporting to give us a list of scholars that he surveyed, how he was classifying them (conservative, skeptical, etc.), and giving the positions he was attributing to them, thus purporting to document his published statistical claims. Given the extreme problems in interpretation that I have documented in his published work, the value of such a chart would be highly dubious.

So severe are these interpretive problems, so systematically inclined does Habermas seem to be to over-optimism and quote mining, so tempted to conflate what he thinks a scholar should affirm with what the scholar actually does affirm, so inclined to over-rely on the "creed" in I Cor. 15 and the supposedly exciting fact that some liberal scholars think it's early, that I have come to wonder whether he has for many years been classifying someone as "affirming group appearances" if that person merely affirms that the first few verses of I Corinthians 15 were composed very early in the history of the church. Obviously, the latter doesn't at all entail the former, and there are scholars (Bart Ehrman is one for sure) who have affirmed the latter (the earliness of the so-called "creed" in I Cor. 15) but do not grant the former (group appearance experiences). There are some comments in the livestream which appear to back up that suspicion of mine. More on that in a later post.

From my perspective, even if all of this were cleared up, there would also remain the weakness of the minimal facts case in defense of the bodily resurrection of Jesus, given the vagueness of (even a group) appearance claim in the absence of any bodily details included in the claim. That is to say, since the MFA doesn't make use of the idea that (at least) the disciples said that they had strong bodily-type experiences in their group meeting(s) with Jesus (touching him, his eating, etc.), or that the phenomenology of their group experiences included such things, the case is very weak as a defense of the bodily resurrection, as opposed to a vision or some non-bodily paranormal experience, such as NT scholar Dale Allison postulates.

But from the perspective of people who still use the MFA in their apologetics work, these recent statements by Habermas are a very big deal, because they strike at the heart of the MFA considered on its own terms. One doesn't have to pay attention to my specific epistemological concerns to know this: The claim that it has been documented that a vast majority of scholars, including skeptics (see Licona's and Habermas's co-written book, The Case for the Resurrection of Jesus, pp. 45-46), affirm the minimal facts and the argument that group hallucinations are extremely improbable (pp. 109, 187-188 in The Case for the Resurrection of Jesus and Licona's The Resurrection of Jesus, pp. 196, footnote 203, and 493) are very important to the MFA. And MFA practitioners have always relied on Habermas's allegedly vast and careful cataloguing research to support statements about what the vast majority of scholars affirm. If, as Livestream Habermas says, he really hasn't documented that these propositions (including one or more group appearance experience) are affirmed by the vast majority of scholars, including skeptics, that cuts the legs out from under the MFA.

Moreover, even if Livestream Habermas is now extremely confused (rather than trying to gaslight) about what he has claimed in writing, it's possible that he's right about what he hasn't rigorously documented. What he has claimed in his own publications, including the most recent, is documentable. What he has actually done in his private research to back up the claims remains, as of August, 2025, somewhat obscure. (Aside, that is, from several disastrously failed interpretations of specific scholars that I've already documented, such as his claim that the Jesus Seminar acknowledges that group appearances are multiply, independently attested. This hardly inspires confidence in any of his unpublished catalogues and lists that remain behind the scenes.) Maybe he has documented some things by his survey of scholarship (say, vast scholarly support across the critical spectrum for the disciples' belief that Jesus was risen in some sense or other) but not others (say, vast scholarly support across the critical spectrum for their having a group appearance experience with intersubjective elements).

I will probably publish a post later on an interesting bit in the livestream where Dr. Licona tries to define "group appearance" in terms that include some intersubjective element and suggests that at least one group experience is a minimal fact. (In Licona's 2010 book, p. 372, at least one group appearance is stated to be historical bedrock. The gloss of some degree of intersubjectivity is an interesting indication of what he means by that.) In such a later post I'll probably also talk about the possibility (hinted at in the livestream, here) that at this point in time Licona will take upon himself the burden of claiming, based on his own research, that there is "very strong" scholarly consensus on the minimal facts, presumably including a group appearance thus defined. This despite the fact that he simultaneously says that he hasn't done the "bean counting" and that Dr. Habermas has studied more than he has of the scholarly landscape--a rather odd comment in the very context where Habermas has just disclaimed having done the "bean counting" either! The question of whether and in what sense Licona and/or Habermas wants to say, and (more important) can defend, at least one group appearance as a minimal fact commanding strong scholarly consensus deserves a post of its own.

Meanwhile, what is the way forward for practitioners of the MFA? Well, if you use the minimal facts argument and your eyes are popping (as they should be) over the news of what Habermas said in this livestream, I do have one suggestion: Consider the maximal data approach instead. Come to the dark side. We have (maximal) cookies!

Friday, July 04, 2025

Another egregious instance of misreading from Habermas's volume 1 [Updated]

In a couple of weeks I'll be starting a new video series on my Youtube channel about the really serious misreadings of skeptical scholars in Habermas's Volume 1 on the resurrection. These follow a pattern of overly optimistic readings of scholars like the participants in the Jesus Seminar, with Habermas routinely thinking incorrectly that they are conceding "amazing" amounts of ground on which a case for the resurrection can be built.

But just today I came across an example in the same volume that is so bizarre that I think it needs to be mentioned separately to show that apparently Habermas, far too often, just cannot read and interpret accurately what he is reading, whether from more liberal or more conservative scholars. In this case the scholar is David Wenham (not to be confused with his father John Wenham). David Wenham is, as far as I know, a Christian scholar. I haven't investigated his work in great detail, but I think he is at least conservative-labeled. So this is an illustration of misreading a Christian scholar.

Habermas is talking about Paul's view of his own experience on the Road to Damascus:

A few researchers have even gone as far as to argue that Paul thought of his own appearance as even “more ‘objective’ and ‘physical’” than the other resurrection appearances! Habermas, Gary R. . On the Resurrection, Volume 1: Evidences (p. 581). Kindle edition.

That seemed like such a strange thing for anyone to think or say that alarm bells immediately went off, given past experience of Habermas's interpretation problems. The two researchers cited in the footnote to this exclamation-mark-emphasized sentence are William Lane Craig, in his older book on evidence for the resurrection, and David Wenham in his book on Paul. 

Update: I thought that this was clear when I first published the post, but it's come to my attention that it apparently was not clear to some defenders of Habermas: This brief discussion of page numbers to Craig's book is an aside. It is not what I am calling "egregious." It is not a big deal objectively. It is not a big deal to me. I never intended to suggest that it was. I was merely discussing the page numbers briefly for the sake of completeness. What is egregious and hugely problematic is the interpretation of Craig and, even worse, of Wenham. It has been suggested to me that a different edition of Craig's book has a discussion of the Damascus road (which I found on p. 58 of the edition that I personally own) on p. 158. For some reason I've not been able to get archive.org to yield the right link to the 1989 edition. But suppose that it's true that the discussion of the Damascus road is on p. 158 in that edition. If so, that's great! This short aside on page numbers is not the important part of this post. The truly wild misinterpretations are the point of this post. So please, let's have no confusion about this. 

As to Craig, the page number that Habermas cites (p. 158) appeared initially to be an incorrect page number, since on p. 158 of the edition of Craig's book that I own, there is nothing about the nature of Paul's Damascus Road experience. P. 58 in my copy (which I carefully looked up precisely because the page number issue isn't the big deal, so I wanted to try as hard as possible to find out what passage of Craig's book Habermas had in mind) is plausible, but on that page Craig doesn't say anything like Habermas's summary in the main text, merely emphasizing that there were some objective aspects to the Damascus Road event, according to Acts, such as the fact that Paul's companions could see a light.

Well, that misinterpretation of Craig in this connection is bad enough. Where did Habermas get the idea that Craig thinks Paul thought that his experience on the Damascus Road was more physical than the other resurrection appearances? My initial guess as to how Habermas came to misinterpret Craig this way was that it was an epicycle on the citation and misinterpretation of Wenham--Wenham citing Craig and then Habermas also citing Craig at this point since Wenham cites him, even though neither of them is saying what Habermas thinks they are saying. Wenham cites this article  by Craig, "The Bodily Resurrection of Jesus." In that article, Craig suggests that Paul's experience might have been as physical as those portrayed in the Gospels, not more so. It appears that this article was incorporated into the 1989 edition of Craig's work on the resurrection, and perhaps Habermas was thrown by Craig's reference there to Paul's doctrine of the resurrection as possibly being more physical than that taugh in the Gospels (due to the great robustness of Paul's theological concept of the resurrection body and perhaps due to the fact that in the Gospels Jesus occasionally disappears), even though Craig is not saying that Paul took his appearance experience to have been more physical than the other appearances. (In fact, as Habermas notes elsewhere, Craig takes the Damascus Road appearance to have been semi-visionary.) 

The real jaw-dropper is the use of the snippet-quote from David Wenham. Habermas completes that snippet quote in his own words--"than the other resurrection appearances." But that isn't what Wenham says at all, in the very place from which Habermas is quoting, namely, Paul: Follower of Jesus or Founder of Christianity, p. 369. Here is what Wenham actually says,

The fact that Paul includes himself in the list of witnesses to the resurrection does not prove that he regarded his experience as identical in character to that of the earlier witnesses. But even if he did, this does not necessarily mean that he saw the earlier experiences as visionary. The opposite inference is arguably more probable, namely, that he did not see his own experience as simply a vision but as something more ‘objective’ and ‘physical’ than the visions that he later experienced and did not categorize as resurrection appearances. (emphasis added)

This is almost unbelievable. Wenham isn't at all suggesting that Paul thought that his own experience on the road to Damascus was more physical than other resurrection appearances. Instead, he's suggesting that Paul thought that his experience on the Damascus Road was more physical than his own later visionary experiences, presumably those such as the one Paul tells about that occurred when he was in Jerusalem, in which Jesus told him to leave quickly, that he was sending him to the Gentiles (Acts 22:17-21) or the one in which he (if he is the man in question) was caught up to heaven and heard things that it is not lawful to repeat (2 Cor. 12:1-4). Wenham is pointing out that Paul doesn't consider other visionary experiences of Jesus that he had to be resurrection appearances. Hence, Wenham reasons, perhaps Paul thought that his initial experience was in some sense more bodily than those and hence more similar to the appearances to the other apostles. (Digression: That isn't my own view. I instead emphasize what Wenham says in the first sentence--that we shouldn't assume too quickly that Paul's inclusion of himself in a list of those who saw the risen Jesus means that he thought he had the very same kind of experiences that they did. I think this is a very important point.)

What Wenham is saying here is absolutely clear. All you have to do is to read the entirety of Wenham's sentence! How exactly it happened that Habermas took a snippet of that sentence, assumed he was understanding it, completely misunderstood it, and summarized it with such an incorrect ending, is just another of those mysteries.

The undeniable fact, however it came about, is that this is a wild misinterpretation of what Wenham clearly says. It's to the point now that I really don't think that we can accept any summary of any scholar that comes from Dr. Habermas that we haven't checked out for ourselves. His research, which is to a great extent a series of statements about the state of scholarship, what this person and that person thinks, etc., is just riddled with severe errors.

Advocates of the minimal facts argument need to know this fact and need to think about what to do in light of it.

Sunday, March 09, 2025

Bayesian analysis, the resurrection, and a partition

This post displays up close the charts used in this Youtube video, which is a follow-up to this recent stream. In the video, which I won't try to reproduce here, I go into more detail about why it is important to use R and ~R in evaluating the evidence for the resurrection (that is, to compare the theory that the resurrection happened to the theory that it didn't happen) rather than comparing R only to some conjunction of specific, alternative explanations of the evidence (e.g., "Jesus didn't rise and the body was stolen and Peter had a hallucination and the stories in the Gospels were invented or embellished, etc.").

A partition, as I emphasize here and in the stream, is a set of mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive propositions.

I argue that comparing the explanatory power of R to that of a "best naturalistic alternative" is epistemically uninformative and obscures the real evidential situation, as would be the case if one did something similar in any non-religious historical case. The video contains various perhaps-surprising probabilistic facts such as...Two incompatible theories can both be confirmed by a body of evidence. Just because there is an odds form of Bayes' Theorem without a partition, it doesn't follow that you can calculate the actual posterior probabilities of the two theories involved without using a partition. 

Here are the images:

Odds form of Bayes' Theorem with a partition:



Bayes factor without a partition:

Thursday, January 16, 2025

Evidentialism and Apostasy, Round 2

Some years ago I wrote a post on whether evidentialism requires apostasy if a Christian believer discovers that he lacks good evidence for Christianity. In that post I endorsed a couple of ministries as examples of places where someone could find evidence for Christianity. At the time I didn't have as much of my own content out on the New Testament, and I also didn't know that William Lane Craig, whose ministry is Reasonable Faith, would endorse (sadly) the idea that the Gospels contain at least some fact-changing literary devices. So, although Reasonable Faith does have a lot of good content on the site, I would now mention that as a qualification on my endorsement of the ministry as an example of where to go to find strong content if you have doubts about Christianity. Also since then Apologetics315 (which I mentioned as another example) has been acquired by another ministry so that only one part of it (the podcast, I believe) is still under the same management.  

On the plus side, the ministry TalkAboutDoubts has been launched since then, run by Jonathan McLatchie, and geared specifically to those who are either good-faith non-Christians looking for answers or Christians troubled by doubts. TAD is strongly evidentialist. Here is my playlist on evidentialism on my Youtube channel.

In the last few days I've had a discussion of evidentialism and the "internal witness of the Holy Spirit" on social media, and I decided that some comments that I made there should be presented in blog post form as well. 

My interlocutor was endorsing the idea of an internal witness of the Holy Spirit (IWHS) that, in his words, "supersedes all rational argument." (Similarly, William Lane Craig calls the IWHS "defeater defeating.") But my interlocutor made a few stipulations: He stipulated that the IWHS may work in a way that is indistinguishable from ordinary means like prayer, Christian fellowship, taking Sacraments, etc. It may, he said, just be the holistic effect of all of those. It could be, but need not be, some sort of separate, sensible or mystical experience or feeling within the person himself. 

I said that using the phrase "supersedes all rational argument" gives the impression that even if the evidence is objectively against Christianity, the IWHS can and should just swamp that fact in the mind of the believer, and I expressed disagreement with any such view. In response he said that of course the evidence, if all is known, objectively supports Christianity but that humans are fallible and limited and that all he meant by "supersedes all rational argument" is that it would supersede the fallible and limited attempts at argument in an individual believer.

He then challenged me with the hypothetical case of a believer who previously based his Christian faith strongly on the minimal facts argument for the resurrection (MFA). I've been highly critical of the force of the MFA, contending that it has been oversold to apologists, lay Christians, and skeptics. My interlocutor asked me to envisage a case in which a believer comes to recognize the weakness of the MFA but for some reason is prevented from finding any better argument. He asked rhetorically if this person should just apostasize.

With that background, here is my lightly revised answer, which I hope will be helpful to someone.

If all you mean is that it supersedes incorrect reasoning due to fallibility and/or lack of information, then this is unhelpful to the person himself in the situation. In fact, a big emphasis upon mere human fallibility and the absence of full information can just as easily (and just as (un)reasonably) undermine Christian faith even when the person does have good information and strong arguments. The Christian with good evidential arguments is still fallible and still lacks omniscience. These facts by themselves don’t justify seeking or hoping for some non-rational guidance toward the truth, and they don’t do so any more in a Christian who has realized that his former arguments for Christianity are weak than in a person who currently thinks that his evidence is strong. In fact, I’ve actually seen people paralyzed by a reflection on mere human limitation so that they are hesitant to accept good arguments. So it’s really quite pointless, and I would say pernicious, to say that there is an IWHS that “supersedes all rational arguments” and then, upon being challenged, to punt to mere human limitation and say that’s what one means.

I definitely don’t think the person in your scenario is obligated to deconvert, at least not instantaneously. But your scenario is overly simple. For example, there are evidences for theism that a person can see for himself, even if all he can articulate self-consciously is something along the lines of, “This all had to come from somewhere,” “Where does beauty come from?” “Humans are radically different from animals, so where did human minds come from in the first place?” etc.

There are also (and this is very important) ways in which the Gospels and Acts have verisimilitude that a person can see for himself. Obviously it helps a lot if he has someone else to point that out to him (which is part of why I do it), but part of the beauty of internal evidences is that they are in principle available to anyone who has the documents in question and has commonsense knowledge about what truthful testimony is like.

You’ve made your concrete hypothetical scenario include his knowing the minimal facts case for Jesus' resurrection and then realizing that it isn’t that strong. But that in itself provides him with some resources for his own investigation. He can also see, if he looks into it, that there is no evidence for merely vision-like experiences on the part of the twelve. So when we abandon the attempt to make much of the “consensus of New Testament scholars” on what the twelve experienced, we are (interestingly) freed up to recognize that scholarly consensus is very messed up, constructing experiences that are contrary to what we find in our closest original sources. He can recognize that a scholar like Allison (say) is reconstructing the resurrection accounts in a circular fashion by arguing that the physical parts were added later just because they are the physical parts. In other words, rejecting the MFA contains in itself some guidance toward the right maximalist path—recognizing the epistemic poverty of mainstream biblical scholarship and focusing on the sources we actually have. Recognizing that the MFA is weak, in large part because it relies on an “appearance fact” that is supposedly “granted by a large majority of scholars,” does not entail continuing to defer to “the consensus of scholarship.”

 The person in your scenario like all of us (I might add) should seek earnestly and sincerely after truth. And because truth in this area—how can a man be right with God, how can he be forgiven, how can his life have meaning, what happens after death, etc.—is so overwhelmingly important, he has an obligation not to settle for a shallow agnosticism. I think he should be able to see for himself the hollowness of Internet skeptics or even pseudo-Christians like Dale Allison.

 You and I both know of deconverts who claim that they “knew all the arguments,” and it’s baloney. They didn't know all the arguments, and they are without excuse, because they could quite readily have found better arguments, or made a better evaluation of the evidence they already had.

You can always dismiss all of these points one at a time by saying, “What if he doesn’t notice that? What if he ‘for some reason’ can’t see any of that? What if…” on and on, including the stipulation that our hypothetical person somehow never stumbles, even in an earnest and long search, upon anything like the ministry of Talk About Doubts or any of the stronger other books and content that are out there.

But remember (this is very important) that you can say something very similar about a person who has never heard of Jesus in the first place. What if a person, from childhood and on into adulthood, is isolated from knowledge of Christianity? What if no missionary comes to him? What if he has no Internet? What if he’s raised to be a suicide bomber? We can always stipulate extreme epistemic disadvantages vis a vis some truth, in this case, the truth of Christianity.

A person who never hears about Jesus and is entirely embedded in an incompatible religion is in a situation that we might call maximally epistemically disfavored. If he grows up and lives and dies without hearing the name of Christ, we have to trust in God’s justice and love as to his eternal destiny.

Or what if a person is somewhat mentally disabled and can’t understand much in the first place, even as an adult?

There is an Amazonian tribe that I have read about that did have missionaries come to them, but the missionaries were not able to make any headway, even after translating the Gospel of Luke into their language, because the tribe has no sense of history beyond (if I recall correctly) three removes back. They would ask, “Did you see these events happen? Did you know someone who saw them happen? Did you know someone who knew someone who saw them happen?” And if the answer to all of these questions was “no,” they immediately lost interest. The social and psychological block on the ability to know history any further back than that was so great that one of the missionaries lost his own faith as a result, because he couldn’t handle the fact that God would allow such ignorance to persist and block the knowledge of the truth of Christianity for an entire people group.

So there’s no reason not to apply a similar point about our own need to trust God concerning a person’s eternal destiny to a person who is much less epistemically disfavored, as in your scenario. (And in this case, as in cases of people who have never heard, we just have to admit that we don't know how God is going to work in this person's life.) This person in your scenario at least has the relevant historical documents and can to some degree evaluate them for himself, and he knows that historical inquiry is possible, Indeed, the very possibility that you raise of an intellectual deconversion implies that he is a thinky kind of person and intelligent and informed enough to realize that this is an important issue and that he needs to be earnestly seeking the truth about it, not settling for some kind of shoulder-shrugging or even bitter and gleeful agnosticism.

But understand something: You have asserted that the IWHS is (at least often, for many people) not detectible but consists in the holistic effect of things like going to church, having Christian friends, taking the sacraments, and prayer. From the epistemic perspective of our hypothetical person who has realized that his former arguments for Christianity are weak and who does not have some kind of mystical, overwhelming experience, all of these factors of social and ritual activities are mirrored in religions that are incompatible with Christianity. From an epistemic perspective, he can’t say to himself, “I have a community of faith here, I have sacramental rituals here, I have prayer practices here, therefore there is some appreciably high probability that Christianity is true.” Perhaps you would agree with that. Your IWHS, especially in its indetectible form, is going to look like something that many other religions have, indeed, that almost all other religions and their practitioners have. But in that case, if you stipulate that after trying for some time to find better evidence, that’s all he has to go on, if you insist on dismissing one after another all the points I’ve made above about his ability to discover more evidence (saying “well, suppose he can’t find that” “suppose he can’t see that” etc.), then in the long run the mere fact that he’s previously been praying, meeting with other believers, confessing sin, and so forth, doesn’t give him reason to believe that their shared beliefs are true. Nor would it be right or accurate for someone to point him to these things as if their mere existence is significant evidence in itself.

If a person in that situation does deconvert, due to his love of truth, while (I will stipulate) continuing for the rest of his life to search for the truth about eternal things, not turning into a deconvert of the usual unpleasant and dismissive type, then we have to trust that God will deal with him justly and lovingly, just as we would trust that for a person raised a Muslim, a Hindu, an animist, raised on a desert island with no religion, etc. Because all of these people are, we are stipulating, evidentially disadvantaged through no fault of their own.

In all of these cases we can hope and even pray that perhaps God would grant to the person an epistemically valuable non-natural experience—for example, some kind of highly unusual dream that suddenly starts occurring, is repeated over and over again, doesn’t have the properties of ordinary dreams, and that directs the person toward a place where he can find better information. (This, I’m told, sometimes happens to Muslims.) That would have some evidential value. Or a private experience with a publicly verifiable tie-down—e.g., "Go to this place and you will meet this person, this is his name," etc., and then you go to that place and meet the person thus described, whom you never have seen before in your life. But we don’t know whether God will do that for any of these people.

So a robust evidentialism does not imply an obligation to deconversion merely upon realizing that one’s former arguments for Christianity are not strong. A person who realizes this should reflect carefully upon what resources he still has available to him and what evidential weight they have, and he should seek to find more information. If we stipulate a case where a person who realizes that is epistemically disfavored in a whole variety of ways that block his acquiring and understanding better evidence for Christianity, even while/after earnestly seeking and pondering, then there is no point in bringing up an IWHS that works “through” his Christian religious practices. And the gerrymandered scenario thus constructed really ends up being importantly similar to more radical cases of epistemic disfavor that we might stipulate, even though in those cases the person in question wasn’t a Christian in the first place. So the idea that a believer has some special anointing or presence of the Holy Spirit isn’t epistemically relevant to the person who is actually in the situation, nor is it relevant to what we should think about what God will definitely provide for him.

(The following paragraphs were not, in this form, contained in my original comment in the social media conversation.) Our own confidence about what God will or won't do for a person depends heavily upon other theological commitments. For example, suppose that you hold to a "once saved always saved" view. Then you'll hold that if this person has really at some time accepted Jesus as Savior, God definitely will do something that will bring him to heaven, even if you don't know what that "something" is. Or to take another example, if you're opposed to any sort of at-death or after-death experience to bring people the truth, then you may hold that both the person who has never heard and an earnest person who deconverts will go to hell and that this doesn't in any way impugn the justice of God. How one thinks election works out in the real world makes a big difference, too, so Calvinism vs. Arminianism come into play. 

I am concerned here mainly to argue that the "internal witness of the Holy Spirit" that "supersedes all rational arguments" really doesn't play a helpful role here. Another point (that I had made earlier in the dialogue in question) is that if you do opt for an IWHS that is detectible as some kind of overwhelming, indescribable, defeater-defeating experience, that doesn't help either, because we know for a fact that a lot of really sincere Christians (myself included) have to say honestly that we don't have such an experience. So the idea that all Christians have this is empirically refuted.

The relationship of evidentialism to the possibility of deconversion is thus complicated. It is possible to envisage a person who is so evidentially disadvantaged that his commitment to truth understandably leads him to some type of deconversion. But it is somewhat artificial to envisage a person who is really that epistemically disadvantaged, especially if he already has access to (say) the Gospels and Acts and the Pauline epistles and is intelligent enough for intellectual deconversion to be a relevant category. If one does insist upon such a scenario, then it's doubtful that God has promised an IWHS that "supersedes all rational argument" and that should prevent that person from deconverting. Instead of postulating such an IWHS, we should trust in the justice, love, and mercy of God in this person's life, just as we would in the case of someone who had never heard of Jesus, and hold the person responsible for continuing to search for evidence about the truth of these matters of ultimate importance.